Results for 'Timothy Hildreth Engstrom'

961 found
Order:
  1.  14
    Foundational Standards and Conversational Style: The Humean Essay as an Issue of Philosophical Genre.Timothy H. Engström - 1997 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 30 (2):150 - 175.
  2.  16
    Translation, Mastery, and Ground; or, Overcoming Some Hermeneutic Fictions.Timothy H. Engström - 2023 - Comparative and Continental Philosophy 15 (3):220-232.
    Comparative philosophy is dependent upon translation, often translations that will help preserve some fundamental commitments: to linguistic mastery, to the recovery or preservation of an original, and to the protection of an authenticity that will ground these commitments. Such a view can sometimes obscure a nostalgia for questionable causes. Comparative philosophy, especially with continental affinities, often relies on two moves: first, a boundary must be found (or produced) between philosophy itself and other forms of writing (literature or fiction, say), to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  48
    A question of style: Nelson Goodman and the writing of theory.Timothy H. Engström - 1992 - Metaphilosophy 23 (4):329-349.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  33
    Ove Arup: Masterbuilder of the Twentieth Century.Timothy H. Engström - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (1):106-109.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  25
    Can We Be Self-Consistent Without Assuming "Realism": A Discussion of Lawrence E. Cahoone's The Ends of Philosophy.Timothy H. Engström - 1999 - Metaphilosophy 30 (1&2):124-134.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Christopher Hookway, "Peirce". [REVIEW]Timothy H. Engstrom - 1989 - Philosophical Quarterly 39 (55):248.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  38
    Accounting for Ethics.Timothy H. Engström - 1994 - Business and Professional Ethics Journal 13 (1-2):41-55.
  8.  67
    Corporate appropriation of privacy: The transformation of the personal and public spheres.Timothy H. Engström - 1997 - Ethics and Behavior 7 (3):239 – 252.
    The primary thesis of this article is that the rights and powers of corporations--to collect, recombine, and resell personal data--have accrued in such a way as to fundamentally circumvent traditional and conventional conceptions of privacy, especially with respect to the sphere of informational privacy. In so doing, informational capitalism has also altered in fundamental ways the public and social sphere itself, the sphere through which one might expect these corporate forces and uses of technology to be controlled.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  42
    On Naturally Embodied Cyborgs.Evan Selinger & Timothy Engström - 2007 - Janus Head 9 (2):553-584.
    This paper examines a specific appeal to philosophical anthropology—Andy Clark's—and the role it plays in shaping his account of our fundamental cyborg humanity." By focusing on the theme of embodiment, we also inquire into how phenomenology might benefit from Clark's account as well as how Clark's account might benefit from further engagement with phenomenology. Throughout, we explore inter- and intra-disciplinary questions that highlight the contribution the philosophy of technology can make to our understanding of embodiment and philosophical anthropology.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  10.  31
    Some Worries about Ocular-centrism.Timothy H. Engström - 2005 - International Studies in Philosophy 37 (4):21-49.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. A moratorium on cyborgs: Computation, cognition, and commerce. [REVIEW]Evan Selinger & Timothy Engström - 2008 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (3):327-341.
    By examining the contingent alliance that has emerged between the computational theory of mind and cyborg theory, we discern some questionable ways in which the literalization of technological metaphors and the over-extension of the “computational” have functioned, not only to influence conceptions of cognition, but also by becoming normative perspectives on how minds and bodies should be transformed, such that they can capitalize on technology’s capacity to enhance cognition and thus amend our sense of what it is to be “human”. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  12.  69
    Interactive computation is interaction with what?: A reply to Clark. [REVIEW]Evan Selinger & Timothy Engström - 2008 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (3):347-348.
    In this response essay, we argue that Andy Clark’s assessment of our position on cyborgs is rooted in a misconception of the notion of “interaction” that we advance.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  64
    Response to Timothy Engström' Review of The Ends of Philosophy.Lawrence E. Cahoone - 1999 - Metaphilosophy 30 (1-2):135-139.
  14. What is the unity of consciousness?Timothy J. Bayne & David J. Chalmers - 2003 - In Axel Cleeremans (ed.), The Unity of Consciousness: Binding, Integration, and Dissociation. Oxford University Press.
    At any given time, a subject has a multiplicity of conscious experiences. A subject might simultaneously have visual experiences of a red book and a green tree, auditory experiences of birds singing, bodily sensations of a faint hunger and a sharp pain in the shoulder, the emotional experience of a certain melancholy, while having a stream of conscious thoughts about the nature of reality. These experiences are distinct from each other: a subject could experience the red book without the singing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  15. Three Faces of Desire.Timothy Schroeder - 2004 - New York, US: Oxford University Press.
    To desire something is a condition familiar to everyone. It is uncontroversial that desiring has something to do with motivation, something to do with pleasure, and something to do with reward. Call these "the three faces of desire." The standard philosophical theory at present holds that the motivational face of desire presents its unique essence--to desire a state of affairs is to be disposed to act so as to bring it about. A familiar but less standard account holds the hedonic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  16. Law-Abiding Causal Decision Theory.Timothy Luke Williamson & Alexander Sandgren - 2023 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 74 (4):899-920.
    In this paper we discuss how Causal Decision Theory should be modified to handle a class of problematic cases involving deterministic laws. Causal Decision Theory, as it stands, is problematically biased against your endorsing deterministic propositions (for example it tells you to deny Newtonian physics, regardless of how confident you are of its truth). Our response is that this is not a problem for Causal Decision Theory per se, but arises because of the standard method for assessing the truth of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17. Is there a Duty to Be a Digital Minimalist?Timothy Aylsworth & Clinton Castro - 2021 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 38 (4):662-673.
    The harms associated with wireless mobile devices (e.g. smartphones) are well documented. They have been linked to anxiety, depression, diminished attention span, sleep disturbance, and decreased relationship satisfaction. Perhaps what is most worrying from a moral perspective, however, is the effect these devices can have on our autonomy. In this article, we argue that there is an obligation to foster and safeguard autonomy in ourselves, and we suggest that wireless mobile devices pose a serious threat to our capacity to fulfill (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  18.  6
    The dynamical alternative.Timothy van Gelder - 1997 - In David Martel Johnson & Christina E. Erneling (eds.), The future of the cognitive revolution. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  53
    Developmental explanation and the ontogeny of birdsong: Nature/nurture redux.Timothy Johnston - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):617-630.
    Despite several decades of criticism, dichotomous thinking about behavioral development remains widespread and influential. This is particularly true in study of birdsong development, where it has become increasingly common to diagnose songs, elements of songs, or precursors of songs as either innate or learned on the basis of isolation-rearing experiments. The theory of sensory templates has encouraged both the dichotomous approach and an emphasis on structural rather than functional aspects of song development. As a result, potentially important lines of investigation (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  20.  75
    The Foundations of Knowledge.Timothy J. McGrew - 1995 - Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    Contemporary epistemology has been moving away from classical foundationalism—the thesis that our empirical knowledge is grounded in perceptual beliefs we know with certainty. McGrew reexamines classical foundationalism and offers a compelling reconstruction and defense of empirical knowledge grounded in perceptual certainty. He articulates and defends a new version of foundationalism and demonstrates how it meets all the standard criticisms. The book offers substantial rebuttals of the arguments of Kuhn and Rorty and demonstrates the value of the classical analytic approach to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  21. Semantic priming: perspectives from memory and word recognition.Timothy P. McNamara - 2005 - New York: Psychology Press.
    Semantic priming has been a focus of research in the cognitive sciences for more than 30 years and is commonly used as a tool for investigating other aspects of perception and cognition, such as word recognition, language comprehension, and knowledge representations. Semantic Priming: Perspectives from Memory and Word Recognition examines empirical and theoretical advancements in the understanding of semantic priming, providing a succinct, in-depth review of this important phenomenon, framed in terms of models of memory and models of word recognition. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  22.  53
    Empiricism in the foundations of cognition.Timothy Childers, Juraj Hvorecký & Ondrej Majer - 2023 - AI and Society 38 (1):67-87.
    This paper traces the empiricist program from early debates between nativism and behaviorism within philosophy, through debates about early connectionist approaches within the cognitive sciences, and up to their recent iterations within the domain of deep learning. We demonstrate how current debates on the nature of cognition via deep network architecture echo some of the core issues from the Chomsky/Quine debate and investigate the strength of support offered by these various lines of research to the empiricist standpoint. Referencing literature from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23. Probabilities and the fine-tuning argument: A sceptical view.Timothy McGrew, Lydia McGrew & and Eric Vestrup - 2001 - Mind 110 (440):1027-1038.
    Proponents of the Fine-Tuning Argument frequently assume that the narrowness of the life-friendly range of fundamental physical constants implies a low probability for the origin of the universe ‘by chance’. We cast this argument in a more rigorous form than is customary and conclude that the narrow intervals do not yield a probability at all because the resulting measure function is non-normalizable. We then consider various attempts to circumvent this problem and argue that they fail.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  24. Metametaphysics and semantics.Timothy Williamson - 2021 - Metaphilosophy 53 (2-3):162-175.
    Metaphilosophy, Volume 53, Issue 2-3, Page 162-175, April 2022.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25. The idea of a logical constant.Timothy McCarthy - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (9):499-523.
  26. The Necessity and Determinacy of Distinctness.Timothy Williamson - 1996 - In David Wiggins, Sabina Lovibond & Stephen G. Williams (eds.), Essays for David Wiggins: identity, truth, and value. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 1-17.
  27. Vagueness: A Global Approach, by Kit Fine.Timothy Williamson - 2022 - Mind 131 (522):675-683.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28. Piece: Contra aesthetics.Timothy Binkley - 1977 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 35 (3):265-277.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  29.  36
    Reconstructing social theory and the Anthropocene.Timothy W. Luke - 2017 - European Journal of Social Theory 20 (1):80-94.
    This study reassesses the concept of the Anthropocene as a new geological age as it is influencing contemporary debates in social theory. As a unit of geological time whose changes are allegedly caused, directly and indirectly, by human beings, this scientific concept challenges the existing constructions of theoretical binaries, such as nature/culture, environment/society, objectivity/subjectivity or happenstance/design, in social theory. The analysis suggests many understandings of the Anthropocene in social theory are politicized over-interpretations of natural events, and these moves appear to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  70
    (2 other versions)Internalism and epistemology : the architecture of reason.Timothy McGrew & Lydia McGrew - 2007 - In Michael Beaney (ed.), The Analytic Turn: Analysis in Early Analytic Philosophy and Phenomenology. New York: Routledge.
    Internalism and Epistemology is a powerful articulation and defense of a classical answer to an enduring question: What is the nature of rational belief? In opposition to prevailing philosophical fashion, the book argues that epistemic externalism leads, not just to skepticism, but to epistemic nihilism - the denial of the very possibility of justification. And it defends a subtle and sophisticated internalism against criticisms that have widely but mistakenly been thought to be decisive. Beginning with an internalist response to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  31.  82
    The Parent Trap: Why Choice-Dependent Moral Theories Fail to Deliver the Asymmetry.Timothy Campbell & Patrick Kaczmarek - forthcoming - Utilitas.
    According to the Asymmetry, creating a miserable person is wrong but failing to create a happy person is permissible, other things being equal. Some attempt to underwrite the Asymmetry by appealing to a choice-dependent moral theory according to which the deontic status of an act depends on whether it is chosen by the agent. We show that all choice-dependent moral theories in the literature are vulnerable to what we call the Parent Trap. These theories imply that the presence of impermissible (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  47
    On Nudging’s Supposed Threat to Rational Decision-Making.Timothy Houk - 2019 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 44 (4):403-422.
    Nudging is a tool of libertarian paternalism. It involves making use of certain psychological tendencies in order to help people make better decisions without restricting their freedom. However, some have argued that nudging is objectionable because it interferes with, or undermines, the rational decision-making of the nudged agents. Opinions differ on why this is objectionable, but the underlying concerns appear to begin with nudging’s threat to rational decision-making. Those who discuss this issue do not make it clear to what this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33. On Tarski on models.Timothy Bays - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (4):1701-1726.
    This paper concerns Tarski’s use of the term “model” in his 1936 paper “On the Concept of Logical Consequence.” Against several of Tarski’s recent defenders, I argue that Tarski employed a non-standard conception of models in that paper. Against Tarski’s detractors, I argue that this non-standard conception is more philosophically plausible than it may appear. Finally, I make a few comments concerning the traditionally puzzling case of Tarski’s ω-rule example.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  34. New norms for teleosemantics.Timothy Schroeder - 2004 - In Hugh Clapin (ed.), Representation in Mind: New Approaches to Mental Representation. Elsevier. pp. 1--91.
    Teleosemantics has a problem: it holds that to have a mind one must have a history, often a long evolutionary history. The solution to the problem is for teleosemanticists to give up on natural selection as the source of natural norms (functions) for neural structures, and to find a different source of natural norms which is not essentially history-involving. Such a source in fact exists, in cybernetic governance. This paper argues for the existence of natural norms derived from cybernetic governance, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  35.  30
    Fundamental issues in the evolutionary psychology of music: Assessing innateness and domain-specificity.Timothy Justus & Jeffrey Hutsler - 2005 - Music Perception 23 (1):1–27.
    Evolutionary psychology often does not sufficiently document the innate constraint and domain specificity required for strong adaptationist argument. We develop these criteria within the domain of music. First, we advocate combining computational, developmental, cross-cultural, and neuroscience research to address the ways in which a domain is innately constrained. Candidate constraints in music include the importance of the octave and other simple pitch ratios, the categorization of the octave into tones, the importance of melodic contour, tonal hierarchies, and principles of grouping (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  36.  90
    Tragedy as a Symbol of Autonomy in Schiller’s Aesthetics.Timothy Stoll - 2022 - British Journal of Aesthetics 63 (1):25-39.
    Schiller’s essays on tragedy attempt to argue that tragic experience is ethically valuable by forging a connection with Kant’s conception of autonomy. Standard interpretations hold that the connection lies in the fact that tragedies depict characters (primarily the hero) exercising autonomy. This paper argues that Schiller also views the experience prompted by tragedy as itself involving autonomy. Drawing on Kant’s discussion of aesthetic “symbols”, Schiller holds that the audience members’ experience at the tragedy is isomorphic with the autonomous exercise of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  55
    Saint Augustine and the Semiotic Trinity.Timothy K. Brown - manuscript
    In this article I briefly explore Saint Augustine’s semiotics. I show how Augustine’s early, bipartite semiotics matured into a tripartite model that maps on to the Holy Trinity, and how this shift allows the Holy Spirit to take on a more distinct role in Augustine’s understanding of meaning. Further, this shift in Augustine’s thinking may help inform contemporary debates in the Augustine literature over how closely Augustine hews to Plotinus’ cosmology.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Realism, Naturalism, and Hazlett’s Challenge Concerning Epistemic Value.Timothy Perrine - 2024 - Journal of Value Inquiry 58 (1):73-91.
    According to Realism about Epistemic Value, there is such a thing as epistemic value and it is appropriate to evaluate things—e.g., beliefs—for epistemic value because there is such a thing as epistemic value. Allan Hazlett's A Luxury of the Understanding is a sustained critique of Realism. Hazlett challenges proponent of Realism to answer explanatory questions while not justifiably violating certain constraints, including two proposed naturalistic constraints. Hazlett argues they cannot. Here I defend Realism. I argue that it is easy for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  81
    Continuity in Leibniz's mature metaphysics.Timothy Crockett - 1999 - Philosophical Studies 94 (1-2):119-138.
    In his early discussion of the structure of matter and motion, Leibniz quite explicitly appeals to Aristotle's characterization of continuity, and seems to adopt something like it as his own. Commentators usually assume that Leibniz continues to understand the notion of continuity in this way for the rest of his life. This paper argues that although he does continue to use something like the Aristotelian conception well into the mature period of his thought, he articulates a second sense of continuity (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  40. Between the subject and sociology: Alfred Schutz's phenomenology of the life-world.Timothy M. Costelloe - 1996 - Human Studies 19 (3):247 - 266.
    In his writings Alfred Schutz identifies an artificiality in the concept of life-world produced by Edmund Husserl's method of reduction. As an alternative, he proposes to assume intersubjectivity as a given of everyday life. This eradicates Husserl's distinction between life-world and natural attitude. The subsequent phenomenological project appears to center upon sociological descriptions of the structures of the life-world rather than on a search for apodictic truth. Schutz, however, actually retains Husserl's emphasis on the subject. A tension then arises between (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  41. Pleasure, displeasure, and representation.Timothy Schroeder - 2001 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31 (4):507-530.
    The object of the present work is to rectify the neglect that pleasure and displeasure have been suffering from in the philosophy of mind, and to give an account of pleasure and displeasure which reveals a striking degree of unity and theoretical tractabiliy underlying the diverse phenomena: a representationalist account.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  42. (1 other version)Improbable knowing.Timothy Williamson - 2011 - In Trent Dougherty (ed.), Evidentialism and its Discontents. Oxford, GB: Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Can we turn the screw on counter-examples to the KK principle (that if one knows that P, one knows that one knows that P)? The idea is to construct cases in which one knows that P, but the epistemic status for one of the proposition that one knows that P is much worse than just one’s not knowing it. Of course, since knowledge is factive, there can’t be cases in which one knows that P and knows that one doesn’t know (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43. The two-envelope paradox resolved.Timothy J. McGrew, David Shier & Harry S. Silverstein - 1997 - Analysis 57 (1):28–33.
  44. Why don’t zebras have machine guns? Adaptation, selection, and constraints in evolutionary theory.Timothy Shanahan - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 39 (1):135-146.
    In an influential paper, Stephen Jay Gould and Richard Lewontin contrasted selection-driven adaptation with phylogenetic, architectural, and developmental constraints as distinct causes of phenotypic evolution. In subsequent publications Gould has elaborated this distinction into one between a narrow “Darwinian Fundamentalist” emphasis on “external functionalist” processes, and a more inclusive “pluralist” emphasis on “internal structuralist” principles. Although theoretical integration of functionalist and structuralist explanations is the ultimate aim, natural selection and internal constraints are treated as distinct causes of evolutionary change. This (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45. Option ranges.Timothy Chappell - 2001 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 18 (2):107–118.
    An option range is a set of alternative actions available to an agent at a given time. I ask how a moral theory’s account of option ranges relates to its recommendations about deliberative procedure (DP) and criterion of rightness (CR). I apply this question to Act Consequentialism (AC), which tells us, at any time, to perform the action with the best consequences in our option range then. If anyone can employ this command as a DP, or assess (direct or indirect) (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46. Evolution, phenotypic selection, and the units of selection.Timothy Shanahan - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (2):210-225.
    In recent years philosophers have attempted to clarify the units of selection controversy in evolutionary biology by offering conceptual analyses of the term 'unit of selection'. A common feature of many of these analyses is an emphasis on the claim that units of selection are entities exhibiting heritable variation in fitness. In this paper I argue that the demand that units of selection be characterized in terms of heritability is unnecessary, as well as undesirable, on historical, theoretical, and philosophical grounds. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47.  77
    On an aristotelian model of scientific explanation.Timothy McCarthy - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (1):159-166.
  48.  59
    States, Activities and Performances.Timothy C. Potts & C. C. W. Taylor - 1965 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 39 (1):65-102.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  49. A quick reply to Putnam's paradox.Timothy Chambers - 2000 - Mind 109 (434):195-197.
  50.  1
    Law and Language.Timothy A. O. Endicott - 2002 - In Jules Coleman & Scott J. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. New York: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 935-968.
    The author argues that philosophers' attempts to use philosophy of language to solve problems of jurisprudence have often failed- the most dramatic failure being that of Jeremy Bentham. H.L.A.Hart made some related mistakes in his creative use of philosophy of language, yet his focus on language still yields some very significant insights for jurisprudence: the context principle (that the correct application of linguistic expressions typically depends on context in ways that are important for jurisprudence), the diversity principle (that grounds of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 961